Expected value is the de-facto standard way of extending preferences over outcomes to preferences over choices under uncertainty. If you have some cardinal-valued valuation of outcomes, then you just multiply that by the probability and you have the expected value of the choice.

That’s great and all, but it’s philosophically interesting to think about whether we need to directly justify preferring choices with higher expected value, or whether we can deduce it from a simpler set of axioms.

I want to focus here on a claim that I think I heard Amanda MacAskill make1: if you accept “dominating” improvements as preferable, you also have to prefer improvements in expected value.

By a “dominating” improvement, I mean one where either the probability or the utility of the other choice is strictly greater, and the other is no worse. So a coin flip with a chance of winning £5 would be preferable to a coin flip where you could win £1; as would simply being given £1.

I think we can actually prove a very similar claim. First, we need to make sure we’re doing cardinal comparisons, not just ordinal ones. So let us assume that we have a utility funtion $u$ over outcomes, and that the probability of an outcome is given by $p$. Furthermore, suppose that the preferability of a choice depends only on its utility and probability. Then we are looking for some function $V(X) = v(u(X), p(X))$ which encodes the preferability of choices, with the implication that if $V(A) = 2 \cdot V(B)$ then $A$ is twice as preferable as $B$.

Then I claim that if $V(X)$ depends linearly and positively on $u(X)$ and $p(X)$ (“linear preferences”) then \(V(X) = EV(X) = u(X) \cdot p(X)\) That is, expected value is the unique function consistent with your preferences.

(We also need an uncontroversial boundary condition: if $p(X) = 0$ or $u(X) = 0$, then $V(X) = 0$.)

The maths

Warning: light calculus ahead.

We want to show $v(u, p) = u \cdot p$.

We can formalise the antecedent of the claim as follows: the partial deriviatives of the valuation function with respect to the utility axis and the probability axis are constant, i.e. \begin{equation} \frac{\partial v}{\partial u} = f(p) \end{equation} \begin{equation} \frac{\partial v}{\partial p} = g(u) \end{equation} where $f$ and $g$ are functions.2

And the boundary conditions: \(v(0, u) = 0\) \(v(p, 0) = 0\)

Integrating equation 1 with respect to $u$ and equation 2 with respect to $p$, we get \begin{equation} v(u, p) = f(p)\cdot u + \phi(p) \end{equation} \begin{equation} v(u, p) = p \cdot g(u) + \psi(u) \end{equation} where $\phi$ and $\psi$ are differentiable functions.

Using our boundary conditions, it is clear that \(0 = v(0, p) = \phi(p)\) and \(0 = v(u, 0) = \psi(u)\)

So we can eliminate $\phi$ and $\psi$ from equations 3 and 4, giving us \(f(p) \cdot u = p \cdot g(u)\) which implies that $f(p) = p$ and $g(u) = u$. Hence $v(u, p) = u \cdot p$ which is precisely the expected value formula.

Philosophical implications

If we can recover expected value from linear preferences, then that means we can take the latter as the prior notion without having to give up expected value. But linear preferences actually distinguish some cases that expected value doesn’t - not in the finite case, but in the infinite case. That’s interesting for philosophical questions that involve infinite utilities (e.g. Pascal’s wager).

In particular, if $u(A) = u(B) = C$ is an infinite cardinal, then no matter what $p(A)$ and $p(B)$ are, the expected values will be the same ($C$). That means that the expected value of being a Christian and being an atheist are the same - both have some chance of getting you into heaven (infinite utility!), and so they have identical expected values.

However, if $p(A) > p(B)$ then $A$ dominates $B$ in probability, and so we should prefer it if we have linear preferences. That means the Pascalian can prefer being a Christian over being an atheist, on the grounds that it is more likely to get them into heaven.

So if you’re a Pascalian looking to avoid some of the stranger implications of accepting the validity of the wager, consider arguing for linear preferences over expected value!

  1. It was in the context of Pascal’s Wager, although her post on the topic doesn’t use it or the argument I make below. 

  2. The right hand sides need to be functions because although the slope is constant for a given $p$ or $u$, it may still vary.